MY TOPIC IS ANIMAL RIGHTS. I ATTACHED THE PDF OF THE PAPER ON ANIMAL RIGHTS FOR PARTS 1 &2 Topic This paper will explain an argument that you have read on your applied ethics topic (animal rights


MY TOPIC IS ANIMAL RIGHTS.


I ATTACHED THE PDF OF THE PAPER


ON


ANIMAL RIGHTS FOR


PARTS


1 &2

Topic

This paper will explain an argument that you have read on your applied ethics topic (animal rights, euthanasia, or global poverty). You will also begin to think of potential objections to this argument. So, in Part 1, explain one of the arguments from the paper you read in 2.2 or 4.2 on your applied ethics topic (animal rights, euthanasia, or global poverty). This will be the same argument that you explained in Applied Discussion 2 or Applied Discussion 3. Then, in Part 2, you will give three potential objections to the argument and explain which objection you think is the best objection to the argument you have chosen (and why).

Specific Instructions for Structuring the Paper

In your final paper, you will be asked to explain and evaluate an argument. This paper is the beginning of that assignment and will function as a draft for the first part of Paper 3. This paper should be organized according to the rubric below, including an introduction and conclusion, as well as Part I and Part II as follows:

  • Part I – Explain the author’s argument in the article that you’ve chosen. In his/her view, what is the correct position to have on the applied ethics issue you chose? What are the reasons that he/she gives in support of his/her view?
  • Part II – Present potential problems for the author’s position. This will not need to be fully developed. Just give three potential problems with the author’s argument (in complete sentences) as bullet points. Make sure that you briefly explain to them so that I know why this is a problem for the author’s argument. After presenting the potential problems, explain which objection is the best objection to the author’s argument, in your view. Make sure to explain why.

Grading

This paper will be graded on content, not length. That being said, you should aim for 2-3 pages. If your paper is too short, you won’t have included all of this assignment’s necessary portions. Your paper should include an introduction, paragraphs devoted to the reasons for your position, and a conclusion. If your paper seems to be a bit long, make sure every word is necessary. You should be able to explain the concepts succinctly as well as clearly.

This is not a research paper, but if you want to use outside sources to explain the specific issue you have chosen to focus on, cite those sources properly. You may use any style that you prefer (APA, MLA, etc.), as long as you are consistent. This should be your own work. Do not plagiarize. See the Syllabus for my policy on this.

Rubric Introduction (10 pts)

The introduction briefly explains the topic discussed in the paper (e.g., the specific issue related to your applied ethics topic) and includes a clear thesis statement. In this paper, your thesis should be a clear statement of the position the author takes  (e.g. “In this paper, I will explain why {author Fname Lname} believes that we ought to….”)

Part I: Explaining the Argument (30 pts)

Accurately represents and clearly explains the author’s argument. This should be organized to clearly express the argument. This section starts by stating the author’s conclusion (e.g., Hooker believes that some forms of euthanasia should be legalized…). Then, the author’s reasoning (the premises of the argument) are explained clearly.

Part II: Potential Objections (20 pts)

States and explains three plausible potential problems with the author’s argument. After briefly explaining objections, the student states (and explains) which of the objections is the strongest objection to the author’s argument.

Conclusion (10 pts)

Succinctly and clearly summarizes the topics discussed and restates the thesis.

Overall Readability and Mechanics (10 pts)

Free of spelling and grammatical errors. Natural and appropriate word choice.

Overall Structure and Organization (10 pts)

Discussion of different topics is clearly indicated in the text—smooth transitions between sections, easy for the reader to follow throughout.

The originality of Thought (10 pts)

Paper demonstrates original and creative critical thinking.

MY TOPIC IS ANIMAL RIGHTS. I ATTACHED THE PDF OF THE PAPER ON ANIMAL RIGHTS FOR PARTS 1 &2 Topic This paper will explain an argument that you have read on your applied ethics topic (animal rights
The Case for Animal Rights Tom Regan 17 How to proceed? We begin by asking how the moral status of animals has been understood by thinkers who deny that animals have rights. Then we test the mettle of their ideas by seeing how well they stand up under the heat of fair criticism. If we start our thinking in this way, we soon find that some people believe that we have no duties directly to animals, that we owe nothing to them, that we can do nothing that wrongs them. Rather, we can do wrong acts that involve animals, and so we have duties regarding them, though none to them. Such views may be called indirect duty views. By way of illustration: sup- pose your neighbor kicks your dog. Then your neighbor has done something wrong. But not to your dog. The wrong that has been done is a wrong to you. After all, it is wrong to upset people, and your neighbor’s kicking your dog upsets you. So you are the one who is wronged, not your dog. Or again: By kicking your dog your neigh- bor damages your property. And since it is wrong to damage another person’s property, your neighbor has done something wrong – to you, of course, not to your dog. Your neighbor no more wrongs your dog than your car would be wronged if the windshield were smashed. Your neighbor’s duties involving your dog are indirect duties to you. More generally, all of our duties regard- ing animals are indirect duties to one another – to humanity. How could someone try to justify such a view? Someone might say that your dog doesn’t feel anything and so isn’t hurt by your neighbor’s kick, doesn’t care about the pain since none is felt, is as unaware of any- thing as is your windshield. Someone might say this, but no rational person will, since, among other considera- tions, such a view will commit anyone who holds it to the position that no human beings feel pain either – that human beings also don’t care about what happens to them. A second possibility is that though both humans and your dog are hurt when kicked, it is only human pain that matters. But, again, no rational person can believe this. Pain is pain wherever it occurs. If your neighbor’s causing you pain is wrong because of the pain that is caused, we cannot rationally ignore or dismiss the moral relevance of the pain that your dog feels. Philosophers who hold indirect duty views – and many still do – have come to understand that they must avoid the two defects just noted: that is, both the view that animals don’t feel anything as well as the idea that only human pain can be morally relevant. Among such thinkers the sort of view now favored is one or another form of what is called contractarianism. Here, very crudely, is the root idea: Morality consists of a set of rules that individuals voluntarily agree to abide by, as we do when we sign a contract (hence the name contractarianism). Those who understand and accept the terms of the contract are covered directly; they have rights created and recognized by, and protected in, the contract. And these contractors can also have protection spelled out for others who, though they lack the ability to understand morality and so cannot sign the contract themselves, are loved or cherished by those who can. Thus young children, for example, are unable to sign contracts and lack rights. But they are protected by the contract nonetheless because of the sentimental interests LaFollette, H. (Ed.). (2014). Ethics in practice : An anthology. Retrieved from http://ebookcentral.proquest.com Created from broward-ebooks on 2019-06-11 06:38:04. Copyright © 2014. John Wiley & Sons, Incorporated. All rights reserved. Ethics in Practice: An Anthology, Fourth Edition. Edited by Hugh LaFollette. 2014 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Published 2014 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc. 193 t h e c a s e f o r a n i m a l r i g h t s of others, most notably their parents. So we have, then, duties involving these children, duties regarding them, but no duties to them. Our duties in their case are indi- rect duties to other human beings, usually their parents. As for animals, since they cannot understand con- tracts, they obviously cannot sign; and since they cannot sign, they have no rights. Like children, however, some animals are the object of the sentimental interest of oth- ers. You, for example, love your dog or cat. So those ani- mals that enough people care about (companion animals, whales, baby seals, the American bald eagle), though they lack rights themselves, will be protected because of the sentimental interests of people. I have, then, according to contractarianism, no duty directly to your dog or any other animal, not even the duty not to cause them pain or suffering; my duty not to hurt them is a duty I have to those people who care about what happens to them. As for other animals, where no or little sentimental interest is present – in the case of farm animals, for example, or laboratory rats – what duties we have grow weaker and weaker, perhaps to the vanishing point. The pain and death they endure, though real, are not wrong if no one cares about them. When it comes to the moral status of animals, contrac- tarianism could be a hard view to refute if it were an adequate theoretical approach to the moral status of human beings. It is not adequate in this latter respect, however, which makes the question of its adequacy in the former case, regarding animals, utterly moot. For con- sider: Morality, according to the (crude) contractarian position before us, consists of rules that people agree to abide by. What people? Well, enough to make a differ – ence – enough, that is, collectively to have the power to enforce the rules that are drawn up in the contract. That is very well and good for the signatories but not so good for anyone who is not asked to sign. And there is nothing in contractarianism of the sort we are discussing that guarantees or requires that everyone will have a chance to participate equally in framing rules of morality. The result is that this approach to ethics could sanction the most blatant forms of social, economic, moral, and polit- ical injustice, ranging from a repressive caste system to systematic racial or sexual discrimination. Might, according to this theory, does make right. Let those who are the victims of injustice suffer as they will. It matters not so long as no one else – no contractor, or too few of them – cares about it. Such a theory takes one’s moral breath away…as if, for example, there would be nothing wrong with apartheid in South Africa if few white South Africans were upset by it. A theory with so little to rec- ommend it at the level of the ethics of our treatment of our fellow humans cannot have anything more to recom- mend it when it comes to the ethics of how we treat our fellow animals. The version of contractarianism just examined is, as I have noted, a crude variety, and in fairness to those of a contractarian persuasion, it must be noted that much more refined, subtle, and ingenious varieties are possible. For example, John Rawls, in his A Theory of Justice, sets forth a version of contractarianism that forces contrac- tors to ignore the accidental features of being a human being – for example, whether one is white or black, male or female, a genius or of modest intellect. Only by ignor – ing such features, Rawls believes, can we ensure that the principles of justice that contractors would agree upon are not based on bias or prejudice. Despite the improve- ment a view such as Rawls’s represents over the cruder forms of contractarianism, it remains deficient: it sys- tematically denies that we have direct duties to those human beings who do not have a sense of justice – young children, for instance, and many mentally retarded humans. And yet it seems reasonably certain that, were we to torture a young child or a retarded elder, we would be doing something that wronged him or her, not some- thing that would be wrong if (and only if) other humans with a sense of justice were upset. And since this is true in the case of these humans, we cannot rationally deny the same in the case of animals. Indirect duty views, then, including the best among them, fail to command our rational assent. Whatever ethical theory we should accept rationally, therefore, it must at least recognize that we have some duties directly to animals, just as we have some duties directly to each other. The next two theories I’ll sketch attempt to meet this requirement. The first I call the cruelty–kindness view. Simply stated, this says that we have a direct duty to be kind to animals and a direct duty not to be cruel to them. Despite the familiar, reassuring ring of these ideas, I do not believe that this view offers an adequate theory. To make this clearer, consider kindness. A kind person acts from a cer – tain type of motive – compassion or concern, for example. And that is a virtue. But there is no guarantee that a kind act is a right act. If I am a generous racist, for example, I will be inclined to act kindly toward members of my own race, favoring their interests above those of others. My kindness would be real and, so far as it goes, good. But I trust it is too obvious to require argument that my kind LaFollette, H. (Ed.). (2014). Ethics in practice : An anthology. Retrieved from http://ebookcentral.proquest.com Created from broward-ebooks on 2019-06-11 06:38:04. Copyright © 2014. John Wiley & Sons, Incorporated. All rights reserved. 194 t o m r e g a n acts may not be above moral reproach – may, in fact, be positively wrong because rooted in injustice. So kindness, notwithstanding its status as a virtue to be encouraged, simply will not carry the weight of a theory of right action.Cruelty fares no better. People or their acts are cruel if they display either a lack of sympathy for or, worse, the presence of enjoyment in another’s suffering. Cruelty in all its guises is a bad thing, a tragic human failing. But just as a person’s being motivated by kindness does not guarantee that he or she does what is right, so the absence of cruelty does not ensure that he or she avoids doing what is wrong. Many people who perform abortions, for example, are not cruel, sadistic people. But that fact alone does not settle the terribly difficult question of the morality of abortion. The case is no different when we examine the ethics of our treatment of animals. So, yes, let us be for kindness and against cruelty. But let us not suppose that being for the one and against the other answers questions about moral right and wrong. Some people think that the theory we are looking for is utilitarianism. A utilitarian accepts two moral princi- ples. The first is that of equality: Everyone’s interests count, and similar interests must be counted as having similar weight or importance. White or black, American or Iranian, human or animal – everyone’s pain or frustra- tion matters, and matters just as much as the equivalent pain or frustration of anyone else. The second principle a utilitarian accepts is that of utility: Do the act that will bring about the best balance between satisfaction and frustration for everyone affected by the outcome. As a utilitarian, then, here is how I am to approach the task of deciding what I morally ought to do: I must ask who will be affected if I choose to do one thing rather than another, how much each individual will be affected, and where the best results are most likely to lie – which option, in other words, is most likely to bring about the best results, the best balance between satisfaction and frustration. That option, whatever it may be, is the one I ought to choose. That is where my moral duty lies. The great appeal of utilitarianism rests with its uncompromising egalitarianism: Everyone’s interests count and count as much as the like interests of everyone else. The kind of odious discrimination that some forms of contractarianism can justify – discrimination based on race or sex, for example – seems disallowed in principle by utilitarianism, as is speciesism, systematic discrimina- tion based on species membership. The equality we find in utilitarianism, however, is not the sort an advocate of animal or human rights should have in mind. Utilitarianism has no room for the equal rights of different individuals because it has no room for their equal inherent value or worth. What has value for the utilitarian is the satisfaction of an individual’s inter – ests, not the individual whose interests they are. A uni- verse in which you satisfy your desire for water, food, and warmth is, other things being equal, better than a uni- verse in which these desires are frustrated. And the same is true in the case of an animal with similar desires. But neither you nor the animal have any value in your own right. Only your feelings do. Here is an analogy to help make the philosophical point clearer: A cup contains different liquids, some- times sweet, sometimes bitter, sometimes a mixture of the two. What has value is the liquids: The sweeter the better, the bitterer the worse. The cup, the container, has no value. It is what goes into it, not what it goes into, that has value. For the utilitarian, you and I are like the cup; we have no value as individuals and thus no equal value. What has value is what goes into us, what we serve as receptacles for; our feelings of satisfaction have positive value, our feelings of frustration negative value. Serious problems arise for utilitarianism when we remind ourselves that it enjoins us to bring about the best consequences. What does this mean? It doesn’t mean the best consequences for me alone, or for my family or friends, or any other person taken individually. No, what we must do is, roughly, as follows: We must add up (some- how!) the separate satisfactions and frustrations of every- one likely to be affected by our choice, the satisfactions in one column, the frustrations in the other. We must total each column for each of the options before us. That is what it means to say the theory is aggregative. And then we must choose that option which is most likely to bring about the best balance of totalled satisfactions over totalled frustrations. Whatever act would lead to this outcome is the one we ought morally to perform – it is where our moral duty lies. And that act quite clearly might not be the same one that would bring about the best results for me personally, or for my family or friends, or for a lab animal. The best aggregated consequences for everyone concerned are not necessarily the best for each individual. That utilitarianism is an aggregative theory – different individuals’ satisfactions or frustrations are added, or summed, or totaled – is the key objection to this theory. My Aunt Bea is old, inactive, a cranky, sour person, LaFollette, H. (Ed.). (2014). Ethics in practice : An anthology. Retrieved from http://ebookcentral.proquest.com Created from broward-ebooks on 2019-06-11 06:38:04. Copyright © 2014. John Wiley & Sons, Incorporated. All rights reserved. 195 t h e c a s e f o r a n i m a l r i g h t s though not physically ill. She prefers to go on living. She is also rather rich, I could make a fortune if I could get my hands on her money, money she intends to give me in any event, after she dies, but which she refuses to give me now. In order to avoid a huge tax bite, I plan to donate a handsome sum of my profits to a local children’s hospital. Many, many children will benefit from my generosity, and much joy will be brought to their parents, relatives, and friends. If I don’t get the money rather soon, all these ambitions will come to naught. The once-in-a-lifetime opportunity to make a real killing will be gone. Why, then, not kill my Aunt Bea? Oh, of course I might get caught. But I’m no fool and, besides, her doctor can be counted on to cooperate (he has an eye for the same investment and I happen to know a good deal about his shady past). The deed can be done…professionally, shall we say. There is very little chance of getting caught. And as for my conscience being guiltridden, I am a resourceful sort of fellow and will take more than sufficient comfort – as I lie on the beach at Acapulco – in contemplating the joy and health I have brought to so many others.Suppose Aunt Bea is killed and the rest of the story comes out as told. Would I have done anything wrong? Anything immoral? One would have thought that I had. Not according to utilitarianism. Since what I have done has brought about the best balance between totaled satis- faction and frustration for all those affected by the out- come, my action is not wrong. Indeed, in killing Aunt Bea the physician and I did what duty required. This same kind of argument can be repeated in all sorts of cases, illustrating, time after time, how the utili- tarian’s position leads to results that impartial people find morally callous. It is wrong to kill my Aunt Bea in the name of bringing about the best results for others. A good end does not justify an evil means. Any adequate moral theory will have to explain why this is so. Utilitarianism fails in this respect and so cannot be the theory we seek. What to do? Where to begin anew? The place to begin, I think, is with the utilitarian’s view of the value of the individual – or, rather, the lack of value. In its place, sup- pose we consider that you and I, for example, do have value as individuals – what we’ll call inherent value. To say we have such value is to say that we are something more than, something different from, mere receptacles. Moreover, to ensure that we do not pave the way for such injustices as slavery or sexual discrimination, we must believe that all who have inherent value have it equally, regardless of their sex, race, religion, birthplace, and so  on. Similarly to be discarded as irrelevant are one’s talents or skills, intelligence and wealth, personality or pathology, whether one is loved and admired or despised and loathed. The genius and the retarded child, the prince and the pauper, the brain surgeon and the fruit vendor, Mother Teresa and the most unscrupulous used- car salesman – all have inherent value, all possess it equally, and all have an equal right to be treated with respect, to be treated in ways that do not reduce them to the status of things, as if they existed as resources for others. My value as an individual is independent of my usefulness to you. Yours is not dependent on your useful- ness to me. For either of us to treat the other in ways that fail to show respect for the other’s independent value is to act immorally, to violate the individual’s rights. Some of the rational virtues of this view – what I call the rights view – should be evident. Unlike (crude) con- tractarianism, for example, the rights view in principle denies the moral tolerability of any and all forms of racial, sexual, or social discrimination; and unlike utili- tarianism, the view in principle denies that we can justify good results by using evil means that violate an individu- al’s rights – denies, for example, that it could be moral to kill my Aunt Bea to harvest beneficial consequences for others. That would be to sanction the disrespectful treat- ment of the individual in the name of the social good, something the rights view will not – categorically will not – ever allow. The rights view, I believe, is rationally the most satis- factory moral theory. It surpasses all other theories in the degree to which it illuminates and explains the founda- tion of our duties to one another – the domain of human morality. On this score it has the best reasons, the best arguments, on its side. Of course, if it were possible to show that only human beings are included within its scope, then a person like myself, who believes in animal rights, would be obliged to look elsewhere. But attempts to limit its scope to humans only can be shown to be rationally defective. Animals, it is true, lack many of the abilities humans possess. They can’t read, do higher mathematics, build a bookcase, or make baba ghanoush. Neither can many human beings, however, and yet we don’t (and shouldn’t) say that they (these humans) therefore have less inherent value, less of a right to be treated with respect, than do others. It is the similarities between those human beings who most clearly, most non- controversially have such value (the people reading this, for example), not our differences, that matter most. And the really crucial, the basic similarity is simply this: We LaFollette, H. (Ed.). (2014). Ethics in practice : An anthology. Retrieved from http://ebookcentral.proquest.com Created from broward-ebooks on 2019-06-11 06:38:04. Copyright © 2014. John Wiley & Sons, Incorporated. All rights reserved. 196 t o m r e g a n are each of us the experiencing subject of a life, a con- scious creature having an individual welfare that has importance to us whatever our usefulness to others. We want and prefer things, believe and feel things, recall and expect things. And all these dimensions of our life, includ- ing our pleasure and pain, our enjoyment and suffering, our satisfaction and frustration, our continued existence or our untimely death – all make a difference to the quality of our life as lived, as experienced, by us as individuals. As the same is true of those animals that concern us (the ones that are eaten and trapped, for example), they too must be viewed as the experiencing subjects of a life, with inherent value of their own.Some there are who resist the idea that animals have inherent value. “Only humans have such value,” they pro- fess. How might this narrow view be defended? Shall we say that only humans have the requisite intelligence, or autonomy, or reason? But there are many, many humans who fail to meet these standards and yet are reasonably viewed as having value above and beyond their usefulness to others. Shall we claim that only humans belong to the right species, the species Homo sapiens? But this is blatant speciesism. Will it be said, then, that all – and only – humans have immortal souls? Then our opponents have their work cut out for them. I am myself not ill-disposed to the proposition that there are immortal souls. Personally, I profoundly hope I have one. But I would not want to rest my position on a controversial ethical issue on the even more controversial question about who or what has an immortal soul. That is to dig one’s hole deeper, not to climb out. Rationally, it is better to resolve moral issues without making more controversial assumptions than are needed. The question of who has inherent value is such a question, one that is resolved more rationally without the introduction of the idea of immortal souls than by its use. Well, perhaps some will say that animals have some inherent value, only less than we have. Once again, how- ever, attempts to defend this view can be shown to lack rational justification. What could be the basis of our having more inherent value than animals? Their lack of reason, or autonomy, or intellect? Only if we are willing to make the same judgment in the case of humans who are similarly deficient. But it is not true that such humans – the retarded child, for example, or the mentally deranged – have less inherent value than you or I. Neither, then, can we ration- ally sustain the view that animals that are like them in being the experiencing subjects of a life have less inherent value. All who have inherent value have it equally, whether they be human animals or not. Inherent value, then, belongs equally to those who are the experiencing subjects of a life. Whether it belongs to  others – to rocks and rivers, trees and glaciers, for example – we do not know and may never know. But neither do we need to know, if we are to make the case for animal rights. We do not need to know, for example, how many people are eligible to vote in the next presidential elec- tion before we can know whether I am. Similarly, we do not need to know how many individuals have inherent value before we can know that some do. When it comes to the case for animal rights, then, what we need to know is whether the animals that, in our culture, are routinely eaten, hunted, and used in our laboratories, for example, are like us in being subjects of a life. And we do know this. We do know that many – literally, billions and bil- lions – of these animals are the subjects of a life in the sense explained and so have inherent value if we do. And since, in order to arrive at the best theory of our duties to one another, we must recognize our equal inherent value as individuals, reason – not sentiment, not emotion – reason compels us to recognize the equal inherent value of these animals and, with this, their equal right to be treated with respect. That, very roughly, is the shape and feel of the case for animal rights. Most of the details of the supporting argu- ment are missing. They are to be found in the book that bears the same title as this essay. 1 Here, the details go begging, and I must, in closing, limit myself to two final points. The first is how the theory that underlies the case for animal rights shows that the animal rights movement is a part of, not antagonistic to, the human rights move- ment. The theory that rationally grounds the rights of animals also grounds the rights of humans. Thus those involved in the animal rights movement are partners in the struggle to secure respect for human rights – the rights of women, for example, or minorities, or workers. The animal rights movement is cut from the same moral cloth as these. Secondly, having set out the broad outlines of the rights view, I can now say why its implications for farming and science, among other fields, are both clear and uncompro- mising. In the case of the use of animals in science, the rights view is categorically abolitionist. Lab animals are not our tasters; we are not their kings. Because these ani- mals are treated routinely, systematically as if their value were reducible to their usefulness to others, they are rou- tinely, systematically treated with a  lack of respect, and thus are their rights routinely, systematically violated. LaFollette, H. (Ed.). (2014). Ethics in practice : An anthology. Retrieved from http://ebookcentral.proquest.com Created from broward-ebooks on 2019-06-11 06:38:04. Copyright © 2014. John Wiley & Sons, Incorporated. All rights reserved. 197 t h e c a s e f o r a n i m a l r i g h t s This is just as true when they are used in trivial, duplica- tive, unnecessary, or unwise research as it is when they are used in studies that hold out real promise of human ben- efits. We can’t justify harming or killing a human being (my Aunt Bea, for example) just for these sorts of reason. Neither can we do so even in the case of so lowly a creature as a laboratory rat. It is not just refinement or reduction that is called for, not just larger, cleaner cages, not just more generous use of anesthesia or the elimination of mul- tiple surgery, not just tidying up the system. It is complete replacement. The best we can do when it comes to using animals in science is – not to use them. That is where our duty lies, according to the rights view.As for commercial animal agriculture, the rights view takes a similar abolitionist position. The fundamental moral wrong here is not that animals are kept in stressful close confinement or in isolation, or that their pain and suffering, their needs and preferences are ignored or discounted. All these are wrong, of course, but they are not the fundamental wrong. They are symptoms and effects of the deeper, systematic wrong that allows these animals to be viewed and treated as lacking independent value, as resources for us – as, indeed, a renewable resource. Giving farm animals more space, more natural environments, more companions does not right the fun- damental wrong, any more than giving lab animals more anesthesia or bigger, cleaner cages would right the fun- damental wrong in their case. Nothing less than the total dissolution of commercial animal agriculture will do this, just as, for similar reasons I won’t develop at length here, morality requires nothing less than the total elimi- nation of hunting and trapping for commercial and sporting ends. The rights view’s implications, then, as I have said, are clear and uncompromising. Note Reprinted by permission from In Defense of Animals (Oxford: Basil Blackwell). Paper presented at the national conference, “Animals and Humans: Ethical Perspectives,” Moorhead State University, Moorhead, MN, April 21–23, 1986. 1 The Case for Animal Rights (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983). LaFollette, H. (Ed.). (2014). Ethics in practice : An anthology. Retrieved from http://ebookcentral.proquest.com Created from broward-ebooks on 2019-06-11 06:38:04. Copyright © 2014. John Wiley & Sons, Incorporated. All rights reserved.

No matter what kind of paper writing service you need, we’ll get it written. Place Your Order Now!